philosophy

Error message

Deprecated function: The each() function is deprecated. This message will be suppressed on further calls in _menu_load_objects() (line 579 of /var/www/drupal-7.x/includes/menu.inc).

Philosophical Counseling And Hellmuth Kaiser On Successful Therapy

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Wed, 08/07/2020 - 2:05am in

In Existential Psychotherapy (Basic Books, New York, 1980), Irvin Yalom writes:

The therapist healed, [Hellmuth] Kaiser believed, simply by being with the patient. Successful therapy requires “that the patient spends sufficient time with a person of certain personality characteristics.” What personality characteristics? Kaiser cited four: (1) an interest in people; (2) theoretical views on psychotherapy that do not interfere with his or her interest in helping the patient to communicate freely; (3) the absence of neurotic patterns that would interfere with the establishment of communication with the patient; (4) the mental disposition of “receptiveness”-being sensitive to duplicity or to the noncommunicative elements in the patient’s behavior. [p. 405; link added]

Note that Kaiser here specifies ‘personality characteristics’; these are not a matter of formal, professional qualification or training. Rather, these speak to the personal dimension of the interaction the therapist brings to her encounters with patient (or client.) They address, most directly, the question of what kind of person, what kind of human being, the therapist is. 

The first, ‘an interest in people,’ is considerably under-specified, but at the least we would expect the therapist to be in the trade because she is genuinely interested in the perplexity of the human condition, and find human beings’ problems to be worthy of sympathy, and generative of empathy. Without this minimal personal qualification (sadly missing in all too many supposed ‘healers’ today) the therapeutic process is doomed. 

Kaiser’s second requirement speaks to letting the therapist’s personal interest in the client trump any preconceived views of therapy; the client’s personality and problems are foremost, and if they do not fit an accepted template of treatment, diagnosis, analysis and prognosis, then so much the worse for the theoretical model.  This requirement means the therapist cannot be rigid and inflexible; the client cannot be shoehorned, brutally, into an existent mold of treatment. Theory is always trumped by the living testimony of the physically realized, concrete client present in the ‘clinic,’ not the abstract, blood-and-flesh-less ‘case’ of therapeutic theory. 

The third is a rather more direct claim on the personality of the therapist. Every therapist, as a human being, suffers from his or her understanding of their life; they often, if not always, require therapy themselves. These by themselves are not an impediment to therapy; however, an established, stubborn neurotic pattern of behavior (excessive, obsessive, selfish, self-interest being an obvious one) that would interfere with listening sympathetically or that results in intolerant, abusive responses to those seeking help, is an obvious disqualification. 

The fourth is an abstract claim but can be made more concrete by considering it an extension and elaboration of the first requirement: the therapist’s interest in people must entail a particular sensitivity–perhaps borne from acute observation, listening, and learning about humans and the human condition–that makes him or her alert to the complexities of a patient’s personality–such as lack of transparency, duplicity, intellectual dishonesty, lack of forthrightness–that can interfere with the therapeutic process.  

These personality characteristics are not designed to be eliminated or created by professional training. You cannot create an interest in people, for instance. In Kaiser’s view then, the therapist is not as much a qualified technician, as much as he is a sympathetic and engaged human being, committed to helping other human beings just like him. Imperfect, but hopeful of learning and reconfiguring themselves. 

Eagleton on Humour

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Tue, 07/07/2020 - 12:12pm in

This review was first published in The Weekend Australian in August 2019.

*

Terry Eagleton, Humour

Yale University Press; $37.99; 224pp

Not long ago a new category appeared, temporarily, on the Netflix homepage, called something like ‘Politically Incorrect Comedy’. Whether this was meant as a warning or a promise, or a bit of both, is hard to say; but there’s no doubt it spoke to something in the culture: a self-consciousness in debates around women and minorities, related to the political moment. When US comics Louis C.K. and Aziz Ansari fell foul of the #MeToo movement, the attendant calumny played into a wider discussion about the relationship between power and joke-making. So too, from a very different direction, did Hannah Gadsby’s Netflix special Nanette, in which Gadsby effectively deconstructs her own set, laying bare the emotional pain beneath the gags. Today humour feels implicitly political in a way that it hasn’t since the 1980s and the rise of so-called ‘alternative comedy’. No wonder that some of the most interesting comics traverse the border between wokeness and outrage, milking the resulting discomfort for laughs.

Ours is an excellent time, in short, to be thinking about the nature of humour, and I can’t imagine a better person to think alongside than Terry Eagleton, the British critic as renowned for his humour as for his unreconstructed radicalism. His new book Humour is an engaging study of how and why we laugh, and at what, and what these things tell us about the kind of animals we are. Ranging from Freud to Frankie Howerd, and from Tristram Shandy to David Brent, it is beautifully written and full of wisdom. It’s also a matchless demonstration of how humour outruns our attempts to understand it, or at least to generalise about its character.

As befits a thinker from the Marxist tradition, Eagleton begins with a chapter on laughter, a phenomenon that speaks to both the creatural and the cultural aspects of the human animal, and to the relationship between the two. Laughter, writes Eagleton, is ‘sound without sense’ – a reminder of our bestial nature, and often frowned upon for that reason. And yet it is also socially coded in a way that reveals our creativity. There’s a big difference between a cackle and a belly laugh, and it follows that humour is similarly diverse. What is the connection – is there a connection – between the wit of Oscar Wilde and the slapstick of Jim Carrey? Why do Germans laugh at Mr Bean and Englishmen fall over when they hear the word ‘knickers’?

Frustratingly for the Big Theory merchants, there are no straightforward answers to these questions, and Eagleton is at his dazzling best when critiquing the different explanatory frameworks. From the ‘release’ thesis favoured by Sigmund Freud, which sees humour in terms of psychological tension, to the idea that humour springs from a sense of the failures and frailties of one’s fellow beings, Eagleton weighs the major theories and concludes that, while each has something to be said for it, none is sufficient on its own to explain the spectacular diversity of humour. Nor is the relationship between humour and power as simple as some commentators assume. It is a contradictory phenomenon, like nationalism – a tool, potentially, of both liberation and oppression. Sometimes it moves in two directions at once. As Eagleton puts it, echoing Freud, ‘In the little insurrection of the wisecrack we can reap the pleasures of rebellion while simultaneously disavowing them, since it is, after all, only a joke.’

The question of power is crucial, of course, and the Russian philosopher Mikhail Bakhtin looms large over this part of the discussion. Bakhtin was a student of the ‘carnivals’ of medieval and Renaissance Europe, and regarded them as a subversive force, turning authority on its head and inverting the priorities of power. His ideas have thus proven attractive to radicals looking for signs that humour is inscribed with a desire to be free from oppression. But here, again, Eagleton is sceptical about the claims being made for humour’s instrumentality. Carnival is drawn to the base and the bodily, but why, asks Eagleton, should such an outlook not also undermine our humanity? ‘If humour can deflate the pompous and pretentious in the name of some more viable conception of human dignity, it can also strike, Iago-like, at the very notion of value, which in turn depends on the possibility of meaning.’

In his final chapter, on politics and humour, Eagleton turns to Trevor Griffiths’ outstanding play Comedians, which is centred on a group of working-class men hoping to make it as stand-up comics, and which feels as relevant today as it did when I first saw it, as a student in the 1980s. Eagleton’s exposition is brilliant, and I found myself wondering if some enterprising theatre could be persuaded to give it another run. We’ll see. But in the meantime this treatise should serve a comparable purpose: to remind us that humour is a lot more complex and contradictory than our cultural politics allow.

The Margins of Philosophy (guest post by Peter Adamson)

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Tue, 07/07/2020 - 12:09am in

Tags 

philosophy

“We need to understand the ‘minor figures’ to understand the ‘major figures’ adequately. But that’s not the only reason to be interested in minor figures, or to bring them to the attention of a wider audience. There is also the fact that apparently minor figures are sometimes major figures.”

The following guest post* is by Peter Adamson, Professor of Late Ancient and Arabic Philosophy at Ludwig Maximilians Universität. He is the author of Philosophy in the Islamic World and he runs the philosophy podcast History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps. He’s on Twitter as @HistPhilosophy.

This post is the fourth installment in the “Philosophy of Popular Philosophy” series, edited by Aaron James Wendland, a philosopher at the Higher School of Economics in Moscow. He tweets @ajwendland.

The Margins of Philosophy
by Peter Adamson

How much would you say you know about Miskawayh? Nāgārjuna? How about Lucrezia Marinella, or Henry Odera Oruka? Probably not much. In fact, you probably haven’t even heard of them.

These thinkers very rarely feature in the teaching of philosophy, and their writings might well be absent at a well-stocked university library in Europe or North America. They do not belong to that select group of philosophers that just about everyone has heard of—Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes—or even to the list of figures that the average professional philosopher has heard of. They are, in short, “minor figures.”

I have given a lot of thought to the importance of such figures, because I produce a series of publicly accessible podcasts on the history of philosophy “without any gaps,” and also because in my own research I often find myself working on them.

I have published a couple of articles about Miskawayh, for instance. He was a historian and well-read philosopher who lived in the eleventh century, and his status as a minor thinker is in truth well-earned. Unlike his near contemporary Avicenna, Miskawayh was not one of the most brilliant and disruptive thinkers in human history. To the contrary, most of his writing is derivative. So why would anyone, even a specialist in philosophy of the Islamic world, spend their time reading and writing about him?

Though Miskawayh was creative in his synthesis of his sources and wrote a treatise on ethics that was fairly influential, the answer is precisely that he was not stunningly innovative. Miskawayh gives us an insight into a mainstream style of philosophy, combining Islamic piety, Aristotelianism, and Neoplatonism, that the more innovative Avicenna was reacting against. This is a common phenomenon: we need to understand the “minor figures” to understand the “major figures” adequately.

But that’s not the only reason to be interested in minor figures, or to bring them to the attention of a wider audience. There is also the fact that apparently minor figures are sometimes major figures. Avicenna is an example. He was the most important philosopher of the Islamic world by a huge margin, and he had far-reaching influence in other cultures too, especially medieval Christendom.

Much the same can be said of the second name I mentioned above, Nāgārjuna. His ingenious critique of the assumption that there are “independently existing” things in the world became the foundation of a whole branch of Buddhist thought, the so-called “Madhyamaka” or “Middle Way.” Nāgārjuna stature in Asian philosophy is similar to that of Kant’s in European philosophy. Nāgārjuna should really be a household name, at least in any house that holds people with an interest in philosophy.

My last two names, Marinella and Oruka, illustrate a further reason for paying attention to so-called “minor figures”: thinkers outside of mainstream philosophy often actively critique that mainstream.

In her On the Nobility and Excellence of Women, written at the end of the sixteenth century, Marinella attacked the misogyny of European culture, reserving special scorn for that most major of figures, Aristotle. Calling Aristotle a “fearful, tyrannical man” for his dismissal of women’s rational capacities, she went against nearly the whole tradition of European philosophical anthropology by arguing in favor of the intellectual and moral equality, if not superiority, of women.

Much more recently, at the end of the twentieth century, Oruka likewise challenged prevailing assumptions about who is capable of producing valuable philosophy. He defended the notion that philosophy can exist in purely oral cultures, developing a project he called “sage philosophy” that involved interviewing outstandingly wise members of traditional African societies.

These “sages” might not have written anything, but they can still represent the philosophical ideas of their people or—even more exciting to Oruka—push against those ideas by setting forth innovative positions of their own. Oruka’s project suggests that philosophy is not what we assume it to be, a tradition of argumentative writing, but something more like a lived wisdom that engages critically with the social setting in which it is produced.

At the moment, we are a long way from making philosophers like Miskawayh, Nāgārjuna, Marinella, and Oruka truly well-known, but steps are being taken in this direction. Podcasts and popular contributions that cast a wider net are raising awareness within the academy and being recommended to students. And I’ve heard from numerous colleagues that they are integrating Islamic philosophy into their teaching.

Doing this doesn’t need to mean devoting an entire course to the topic. Some associates and I recently wrote a series of blog posts for the American Philosophical Association suggesting how to integrate lesser-known figures from the Islamic world, India, and China into thematic courses on epistemology, ethics, and so on.

Of course, the “minor” figures mentioned above give you only a handful of examples. But I hope they suffice to convince you that it is worthwhile making less-known philosophers better-known. They can help provide context to understand the philosophical giants we already care about; they can turn out to be giants worth caring about in their own right; and they can change our ideas about what philosophy itself is.

[image: Mir ‘Imad al-Hasani, Album Page with Calligraphic Composition]

The post The Margins of Philosophy (guest post by Peter Adamson) appeared first on Daily Nous.

Online Philosophy Resources Weekly Update

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Mon, 06/07/2020 - 10:36pm in

Here’s the report on new and revised entries in online philosophy resources and new reviews of philosophy books.

SEP

New:

Revised:

  1. Collingwood’s Aesthetics, by Gary Kemp.

IEP 

  1. Kit Fine, by Mike Raven (Victoria).

NDPR

  1. Philosophers LLC. reviews Au Revoir, by Anastasia Gutting.
  2. Jeff McMahan (Oxford) reviews The Quality of Life: Aristotle Revised (Oxford), by Richard Kraut.
  3. Scott Soames (Southern California) reviews Frege’s Detour: An Essay on Meaning, Reference, and Truth (Oxford), by John Perry.

Wireless Philosophy

1000-Word Philosophy

  1. Ethics and the Expected Consequences of Voting, by Thomas Metcalf (Spring Hill College).

Compiled by Michael Glawson.

The post Online Philosophy Resources Weekly Update appeared first on Daily Nous.

What works: getting to the land of ‘how’: Complete essay

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Mon, 06/07/2020 - 8:30pm in

Note, this essay was published in three parts in the Mandarin and is published in consolidated form (complete with its footnotes) here.

It is impossible to remember, until one gets in the country … that they care about their experiment more than about making things work.

John Maynard Keynes on Soviet Russia, to Lady Ottoline Morrell, May 2, 1928.[1]

Part One
I.         The land of ‘what’ and the land of ‘how’

From at least the years of the ‘third way’ in the 1990s under Blair and Clinton, we’ve been hearing what governments need to do to address our various social problems. Again and again, ‘thought leaders’ tell us what we must do – move beyond one-size-fits-all services to ‘joined up government’ to ensuring that programs do things ‘with’ people rather than ‘to’ them. Plausible as they are, these ideas have barely been tested. Because if they tell us what we have to do, we’ve scarcely learned how.

At the outset there seemed to be a seductive straightforwardness to getting to how. As Bill Clinton put it “nearly every problem has been solved by someone, somewhere”. The challenge was “to find out what works and scale it up”. For me these words stand as a creation myth of the problem I want to address. They even show us original sin, because if you pay close attention there it is! Clinton suggests we learn how to solve our problems by learning a ‘what’ – what works – and then scaling it.

Yet here we are nearly three decades on and despite numerous promising innovations in small scale programs, they all share the same fate. It’s hard to think of a single example of action to address social problems that’s started small and been ‘‘scaled’ as Clinton proposed. Yet despite endless inquiries into our failure to address social problems – for instance aboriginal or multi-generational disadvantage and endless restructurings and resettings of policy in response, we’ve never got far. Peter Shergold lamented the problem in 2005.[2] Yet despite a term as the nation’s chief public servant, he conceded in 2013 that the problem remains.[3]

This is the first installment of a three part essay which itself is part of a larger project. In this article I’ll set the stage showing the subtlety and depth of the problem. For, when it’s pointed out, we all understand that there’s a difference between ‘knowing what’ the rules of tennis or chess are and ‘knowing how’ to play. My claim is that in all kinds of ways we insensibly confuse the the two and so substitute ‘knowing what’ (or ‘knowing that’) and knowing-how. In this first part of this essay, I’ll show how this happens in our universities and the professions they teach. In the second, I’ll show how this occurs in government agencies and programs. The third part concludes with a look at recent initiatives like nudge units and What Works Centres that seek to foster greater ‘knowing how’ and innovation in government. The key to their success so far has been the way they bolt on to business-as-usual and, in so doing, improve it. This essay is written to try to articulate how they might envisage a more ambitious future.

II.         From the foundations to the commanding heights

Our confusion in understanding the distinction between ‘knowing that’ and ‘knowing how’ goes all the way back to our language itself. The lives we lead are built on a vast repertoire of tacit knowhow that we don’t and indeed can’t make fully explicit. Prosaic examples include anything taught by doing like riding a bike or kicking a football. But this stretches to skills you use all the time. Like those you’re using now – to help you interpret the strange squiggles your eyes are scanning while your brain converts them insensibly into meaning. These tacit skills are fundamental to making social and economic systems work, not least the judgements people make about what constitutes good work and what does not.

This issue is not discussed much in public administration or in economics, but one tradition has developed its ideas with close attention to it. As John Gray explains, Friedrich Hayek’s case for the indispensability of markets wasn’t just that they harnessed explicit local knowledge and expertise distributed throughout the economy. It is:

the far more fundamental problem of the practical knowledge on which economic life depends being embodied in skills and habits, which change as society changes and which are rarely expressible in theoretical or technical terms.[4]

Hayek further intimated the prospect that English speakers were disadvantaged in attending to the distinction between ‘knowing that’ and ‘knowing how’. The English language provides a more limited vocabulary for appreciating the distinction than many other European languages such as German. It was largely invisible to English speaking philosophy until Gilbert Ryle published on it in 1946.[5] There’s much to be unpacked here. In the academy the status of ‘knowing that’ is far higher than ‘knowing how’. I expect this is particularly pronounced in the Anglosphere. Knowhow is often gained via learning-by-doing within an apprenticeship rather than via the discursive methods of traditional teaching. This apprenticeship tradition remains much stronger in Germanic and Northern European cultures than in the Anglosphere.[6]

The great economist, cyberneticist and organisational theorist Herbert Simon is one of the few English speaking thinkers to foreground this distinction between ‘knowing what’ and ‘knowing how’.[7] For him, the distinction marks a faultline: On one side lie the sciences; on the other the professions. Sciences are for knowing what is given and necessary in nature. By contrast, the professions, such as engineering, medicine, business, architecture, and painting are for doing. They’re concerned “not with the necessary but with the contingent, not with how things are but with how they might be”.

In short, Simon concludes, the professions are all fundamentally about design – that is, with devising “courses of action aimed at changing existing situations into preferred ones”. This highlights the irony of a process that reached its apogee in the decades after WWII. As they sought to clothe themselves in the mantle of science the university faculties teaching the professions emptied their curricula of design content:

Engineering schools gradually became schools of physics and mathematics; medical schools became schools of biological science; business schools became schools of finite mathematics. The use of adjectives like “applied” concealed, but did not change, the fact. It simply meant that in the professional schools those topics were selected from mathematics and the natural sciences for emphasis which were thought to be most nearly relevant to professional practice. It did not mean that design continued to be taught, as distinguished from analysis.

Any economics graduate will appreciate Simon’s point. As he put it, “in terms of the prevailing norms, academic respectability calls for subject matter that is intellectually tough, analytic, formalizable, and teachable”. In Part Two I show these same confusions turning up in the world of work. There, the drivers are not only the greater prestige of ‘knowing that’ over ‘knowing how’ but also its greater ‘legibility’ to systems, particularly to those at the top.

Part Two
III.         From the commanding heights to everyday routines

The big public sector careers are built in the land of ‘what’ – that is in designing and administering policy in our social services systems in our capital cities. Meanwhile the land of ‘how’ is the land of ‘street-level bureaucrats’. It’s out in the sticks. And that’s inauspicious territory from which to build a public sector career. It’s a mark of how disconnected from the how those in the centre are that, as I’ve previously documented, they imagine that something like a market in ‘what works’ either already exists or will somehow construct itself around opportunities as they present themselves. And so, somehow, our complete failure to build even the rudiments of a system that might detect and then seek to expand what works wherever we find it goes unremarked. This is true of casual discussion, of senior bureaucratic and political leaders’ prepared speeches, in academic work and in the stream of independent reports every year or so including the recent comprehensive Thodey Review of the public service.

Of course people understand the difference in principle between ‘knowing what’ and ‘knowing how’ when their attention is drawn to the distinction. But they’re generally unaware of the way ‘knowing what’ has come to substitute for knowing how throughout their world. Because organisations and systems can’t easily scrutinise their agents’ know-how, it is made legible to them via the proxy of knowing what. Employees’ credentials come to stand for their know-how. As entrepreneur and essayist Paul Graham has written, this process begins at school and most of the confusion between the two occurs insensibly:

For me, as for most students, the measurement of what I was learning completely dominated actual learning in college. … Getting a good grade in a class on x is so different from learning a lot about x that you have to choose one or the other, and you can’t blame students if they choose grades. Everyone judges them by their grades — graduate programs, employers, scholarships, even their own parents.[8]

It took Graham the best part of his professional life to understand what was really going on, and how hard it was to get the high achievers he mentored in start-ups to focus on the real ‘how’ of their job – how to make great products – rather than looking round for tests to ‘hack’. (In that context this involved looking for tips and tricks to attract the money of investors and customers).

Where know-how pervades an organisation, the damage done by these expedients will often be contained. They may be a dominant consideration in recruitment, but then the actual contribution of those recruited can loom larger in the system’s apprehension of their abilities and its provision of training and further career progression. This will often be the case where a failure of know-how is made conspicuous by failure – as in the case of engineering – and/or where professional knowledge is given independent status within organisations – as with medicine. Elsewhere, the professions are both less well trained and enjoy less independent status. This is true in teaching, social work and public administration.

Here the various makeshifts by which organisations govern know-how – such as KPIs – can take on a life of their own just as tests come to dominate what is learned in school. This process is also a major factor in consulting. The biggest firms – now known as ‘brands’ – deliver professional services from people with some of the best resumes available in law, engineering, policy development, management, communications and PR. And whether they really have the appropriate know-how for the task at hand, or however well their incentives align with the longer term tasks to which they contribute, no-one ever got sacked for hiring them.

The point made in the previous installment of this essay regarding the disconnect between knowing that and knowing how in the professions might seem somewhat rarified. After all, economists and engineers tend not to deliver services on the ground. Yet the imaginative landscape implied by their discipline and other high status professions aspiring to scientific status casts a long shadow. The tendency for ‘knowing what’ – or various immitations of it – to take precedence over ‘knowing how’ characterises the way social policy is designed and delivered.[9]

Thus for instance, the New Zealand Treasury is proud of its wellbeing framework on which it’s worked for around a decade – and far more than Australia’s desultory exercise. On the arrival of a Prime Minister Ardern who was keen to bring wellbeing into the central objectives of government policy, it enabled the rapid production of a wellbeing ‘dashboard’ for policymakers. In principle it can answer questions like “what is the level of wellbeing amongst Māori in Christchurch?”

This information may prove to be valuable or otherwise. But it’s from the land of ‘what’ and tells us surprisingly little if we want to visit the land of ‘how’. It offers no direct insights into how one might improve the wellbeing of Māori in the Christchurch area. Yet this was surely the point of the exercise. As I’ve documented elsewhere, this is par for the course in most jurisdictions. We might equally invest in a dashboard showing us the prevalence of headaches without noting that people have used the salicylic acid occurring naturally in willow bark to alleviate headaches for three and a half millennia. It is now marketed as asprin.

When embarking on some difficult new venture, or the refurbishment of an old one, the habit is not to start from a stocktake of what knowhow and capability is and is not available to the system in the field. Nor is it to identify where performance has been best to ensure that those people and their insights help steer the process of lifting the system’s capability more broadly. This would be analogous to the way evolution and markets build from outbreaks of what works best wherever they occur in the field rather than designing and imposing a plan from the top-down.

Rather than a stocktake of capabilities of the existing knowhow of the organisation, the construction of frameworks becomes alluring. Frameworks are from the land of ‘what’. It might be the case that some frameworks embody very deep and rigorous thought. But no-one scrutinising them from the outside could ever tell. For, just as certain approaches to economics are proud of their ability to ignore whether their subject is silicon chips or potato chips, so, frameworks are written in a language which is largely independent of the work being done. They tie together inputs, outputs, outcomes and an overarching ‘vision’ all strung together with pleasing abstract nouns or adjectives. Words like ‘equitable’, ‘effective’, ‘efficient’, ‘accountable’ and ‘sustainable’ often figure as if asserting them vouchsafed their presence in the program.

All this makes the construction of frameworks an ideal displacement activity for the generalists running the show. It shows them to be busy leading and organising the troops while keeping them entirely insulated from having any skin in the game. If a bridge falls down or billions go missing, that word ‘accountable’ is in the framework for a reason. The malefactors can be rounded up from the land of ‘how’. As if betraying unquiet consciences at this vacuity, such framework documents frequently arrange their pleasing words into strategic diagrams which suggest specific relationships between them. Yet it’s surprising – or perhaps unsurprising – how gratuitous these diagrams are. Or on occasion worse. For on taking them seriously, it’s remarkable how often the relationships they imply actually make no sense or worse, betray the ultimate confusion and magical thinking at the heart of the project they illustrate.

At this point, it may have occurred to you that know-how is much harder to govern, and so a much harder thing to deliver than knowing what. It’s also often much less ‘scalable’. So not only have I no magic wand to wave that will fix it all, but if I did, I would probably be perpetrating the very thing that I’m critiquing – which is fads peddled by ‘thought leaders’ in TED talks and endless elite international events repackaging third way nostrums from the land of ‘what’ when we desperately want admission to the land of ‘how’.  But in Part Three, I’ll take a look at three new kinds of institutions designed to win new know-how and scale it in government service delivery: Government innovation ‘labs’, behavioural insights units and What Works Centres. The key to their success so far has been the way they bolt on to business-as-usual and, in so doing, improve it. But as I’ll explain, if these acorns are to grow into the oak trees that might herald a mature system in which know-how is won and ‘scaled’, they’ll have to move beyond their own tendencies to substitute know-ledge for the more difficult and distant destination of know-how.

Part Three
IV.         New ways of institutionalising know-how

Given governments’ evident failure in rising to the challenges of the third way, it’s not surprising that there are various promising initiatives intended to pursue better know-how in government. They are usually thought of as part of the ‘innovation in government’ agenda. Their contribution both began, and remains incremental. This is unsurprising given that these initiatives must germinate and grow within a much larger incumbent system to which they must make themselves useful. My critique below is not offered in any spirit of disapproval – rather the opposite. Instead, it pursues a fond hope that, with sufficient care to understand our situation and patient work to improve it, the initiatives we see before us are but acorns that might grow to a forest of oak trees over the next few decades.

Government innovation labs are a small, and so far relatively tokenistic nod towards the idea that innovation in government agencies cannot be specified in systematic ‘knowing what’ that might be imported from elsewhere, but must be won in the development of new ‘knowing how’. They house activities such as prototyping, human-centred design and small scale experiment where failure is regarded as a normal and necessary foundation for working towards success. They have certainly led to some worthwhile new initiatives and improvements on old ones.[10]

Behavioural insights or ‘nudge’ units have also proliferated, receiving far more recognition and status than labs, perhaps because of their alignment with a new development in the academy – the import of psychological research into economics known as ‘behavioural economics’. One of their stocks-in-trade is A/B testing which was pioneered in early 20th century media and subsequently adopted far more widely. This is used to optimise outcomes from government communication such as tax arrears letters and SMS reminders.

Once such know-how is won, it is typically easily scaled – not requiring any particular skill from those that use it. Behavioural insights units also capture the know-how residing in academic journals – for instance about the setting of defaults to optimise outcomes – to convert it into a ‘what’ that can be readily ‘scaled’ or applied system wide. Still the focus on testing the usefulness of interventions large and small before deploying them – via A/B testing or more elaborate randomised controlled trials – has produced large benefits compared with the small scale of the investment in such units.

Both nudge units and innovation labs have been helpful in introducing new ways of working. Thus for instance, as David Halpern reports, his own behavioural insights or BI unit embraced “a healthy dose of ethnography – a ‘method acting’ approach to policy – as an essential ingredient in translating BI-inspired ideas into the real world”. Likewise the Unit sought to maximise the use of feedback, not just to manipulate behaviour in presumptively beneficial ways, but also to ensure government systems themselves were continually improving their performance.[11] One might have hoped such methods were already well entrenched in social service policy and delivery. But the sad truth is that too often they’ve been conspicuously absent.

‘What Works Centres’ are another such institution. As Mulgan and Breckon put it the idea behind them is “very simple”:

It’s to help busy people who make decisions access the best available knowledge about what works. … They do this by orchestrating the best available evidence and making it usable for policymakers, for public servants, and for the wider public. Experience has shown again and again that it’s not enough to gather evidence and put it into repositories. Unless users are closely involved in how evidence is shaped and made accessible, behaviour is unlikely to change.

The proponents of What Works Centres are aware of the problems of context. Thus in one article Mulgan stresses the need to ask not just ‘what works’, but “for who, when, where and with who.” Just as with the other kinds of institutions mentioned above, What Works centres try to involve practitioners and to tailor their output to be useful to practitioners in the field. In this they help cultivate the public goods of professional activity, most particularly by nurturing the knowledge of communities of practice. They also stress the need for building “intelligent feedback loops” into service delivery.

Still, just as there’s much to the adage that what gets measured gets managed, so what gets codified in this process tends to be the core product of tips and tricks that ‘work’ with the caveats about context being downplayed. Thus for instance Mulgan celebrates the Crime Reduction Toolkit as a “good example” of the way What Works centres translate research into “useful products, distilling complex patterns into formats that can be used by busy professionals” in this case producing “a Which?-style guide at the College of Policing that weighs up the effectiveness of things like correctional bootcamps, CCTV or electronic tagging”. The tool is a table in which one can read off hundreds of potential interventions and see how they rank in five fields which rate the quality of the evidence available on the extent of their impact on crime, how they work, where they work, how to implement them and what they cost.[12]

Figure: The Crime Reduction Toolkit

V.         Conclusion

For as long as we continue to characterise what we’re trying to achieve with a name as amorphous as an ‘innovation agenda’, it’s hard to imagine it rising above anything more than being an add-on to business-as-usual – which of course guarantees that it will ultimately be constrained by the procedures and imperatives of business-as-usual. All the new initiatives I’ve identified operate as if the most prized kind of know-how they seek to generate is ‘tips and tricks’ – which is to say know-how that’s been codified so that it is a ‘what’ that can be applied more widely and ideally ‘scaled’ into whole systems. The A/B testing mentioned above provides the paradigm case of special-purpose know-how that, once won, can be scaled as a ‘what’. Given the straightforwardness of such techniques, it’s not too much to hope that they are increasingly built in to business-as-usual wherever they can be useful.

That such measures should be a priority makes perfect sense if one wishes to demonstrate ‘early wins’ on which one can gain some prestige within the system and parley it into building something more substantial. But to succeed in properly reorienting government service delivery towards knowing how to perform the difficult tasks society gives it – including most importantly of all, to identify and straightforwardly communicate where it has no such knowhow – would require a massive transformation of the system we have today. I intend to sketch possible elements of that transformation in subsequent essays. I have already sketched one such institution – an Evaluator General. It seeks to build accountability not on the accountability of those lower in a hierarchy to those above, but on those in the system – particularly the ‘street level bureaucrats’ out in the field – holding themselves to account for their practical achievements. Yet to effectively avoid wishful thinking such self-accountability needs to run the gauntlet of independent validation by others with domain expertise.

It is by way of such mechanisms that we might aspire to rebuild the know-how of the professions themselves around similar principles, rather than build them as they have been hitherto, on foundations of independence and prestige rendered accountable to a community of practice but much less to independent verification. But before doing that, in the next essay I want to sketch some additional kinds of cognition and action that systems need to take account of. Because social knowledge and cognition and so, improved social outcomes, require more than knowing how. They require both knowing-with and feeling-with others, and some faith in the likelihood of that taking place.

* Thanks to Gene Tunny and Paul Frijters for helpful comments on earlier drafts.

[1] Skidelsky, Robert, 1994. John Maynard Keynes, vol. 2: The Economist as Savior 1920–1937 (New York: Allen Lane, p. 236.

[2] As Shergold put it:

If there were a single cultural predilection in the Australian Public Service that I could change, it would be the unspoken belief of many that contributing to the development of government policy is a higher order function – more prestigious, more influential, more exciting – than delivering results. Perhaps it is because I have spent so much of my career in line agencies, learning to deliver indigenous, employment, small business, and education programs that I react so strongly against this tendency.

Mendham, Tim, 2005. “The State of Project Management”, CIO Magazine, 1 Nov, at https://www.cio.com/article/3494549/the-state-of-project-management.html

[3] As he put it in 2013:

Too much innovation remains at the margin of public administration. Opportunities are only half‐seized; new modes of service delivery begin and end their working lives as ‘demonstration projects’ or ‘pilots’, and creative solutions become progressively undermined by risk aversion and a plethora of bureaucratic guidelines.

Shergold, P. 2013 “My Hopes for a Public Service for the Future”, Australian Journal of Public Administration; March 2013, Vol. 72, Issue 1, p.7-13 at p. 7, also available at this link https://www.apsreview.gov.au/file/174/download?token=d5v23YKW. Note that it exists elsewhere. See for instance Savoie regarding Canada’s public service:

The ambitious know full well that the road to the top is through policy, generating ideas, managing the blame game, being visible in Ottawa circles, and central agencies, not through program management.

Donald J. Savoie “What Is Government Good At? A Canadian Answer” 2015.

[4] Thus Hayek often quoted the great Alfred North Whitehead:

It is a profoundly erroneous truism, repeated by all copy-books and by eminent people when they are making speeches, that we should cultivate the habit of thinking of what we are doing. The precise opposite is the case. Civilisation advances by extending the number of operations we can perform without thinking about them.

[5] Here’s Hayek citing that article:

The almost complete loss of the original connotation of ‘can’ in English, where it can scarcely any longer be used in the infinitive form, is … an obstacle to the easy discussion of these problems …. If a German says Ich weiß, wie man Tennis spielt this does not necessarily imply that he knows how to play tennis, which a German would express by saying Ich kann Tennis spielen. In German the former phrase states the explicit knowledge of the rules of the game and may – if the speaker had made special motion studies – refer to the rules by which the skill of a player can be described, a skill which the speaker who claims to know these rules need not possess. German, in fact, has three terms for the English ‘to know’: wissen, corresponding to ‘know that’, kennen, corresponding to ‘be acquainted with’, and können, corresponding to ‘know-how’.

Hayek, F.A., 1962. “Rules, perception and intelligibility”, in Hayek, 2014. The Market And Other Orders, The collected works of F. A. Hayek, Volume XV, Bruce Caldwell (ed), pp 232-53 at p. 233.

[6] In English speaking countries university-based know-ledge is the fulcrum of professional training. Apprenticeship based learning-by-doing typically supplements this only to the extent that the alternative would produce obvious dysfunction. Outside of lower status manual trades, in medicine, law and engineering, practice-based training is now merely part of the pathway from university into the workforce via internships.

[7] For readers interested in economists, it was one of the things that drove him to dismiss profit maximisation as a good way to think about what business managers did. It might be ‘what’ they thought they did, but the moment you focused on how they did it you had to imagine them doing something more prosaic and grounded in their practice – which Simon called ‘satisficing’.

[8] He continues:

Why did founders tie themselves in knots doing the wrong things when the answer was right in front of them? Because that was what they’d been trained to do. Their education had taught them that the way to win was to hack the test. And without even telling them they were being trained to do this. The younger ones, the recent graduates, had never faced a non-artificial test. They thought this was just how the world worked: that the first thing you did, when facing any kind of challenge, was to figure out what the trick was for hacking the test. …There are certainly big chunks of the world where the way to win is to hack the test.

[9] In economics, I’ve documented how this occurs with the crude distinction between ‘positive’ and ‘normative’ economics. The considerations issues raised by Simon above would be news to almost all economists – including professors of their field. Given this, economists imagine that normative conclusions about economic policy must follow relatively straightforwardly from positive models of the economy. (Yet the distinction between positive and normative should be the same distinction Simon references above between ‘applied’ analysis and ‘design’ or the knowhow to effect “courses of action aimed at changing existing situations into preferred ones”.)

[10] For an example of what looks like useful work labs can do see “Box 4.6: The case of New Zealand drivers’ licences” in Lateral Economics, 2017, “Through thick and thin: Cultivating self-organisation in Australia’s regions”, July at p. 40.

[11] See e.g.. Halpern, David, 1915 Inside the Nudge Unit, pp. 211–212.

[12] Thus for instance the What Works Centre for Crime Reduction promulgates an online tool that “allows users to weigh up evidence on the impact, cost and implementation of different interventions and use this to help shape their crime reduction efforts”. It lists numerous interventions like “Victim Offender Mediation”. The centre says that it has high quality evidence on this intervention, and that it produces a decrease in crime, but adds that “some studies suggest an increase”. Be that as it may, it does not take much imagination to believe that such interventions could be done well or badly depending on the know-how of those responsible for them. But it’s only the know-ledge that features prominently. Moreover if know-how was the heart of success, this could remain largely invisible to this methodology. It suggests an alternative methodology – in which more authority and resources are given to the individuals and teams who are seen to have demonstrated their knowhow with superior results. And this hints at a polycentric order of professionalism.

Firework Bans and Wearing Masks

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Sat, 04/07/2020 - 10:41pm in

Tags 

philosophy

“But my freedom” doesn’t work as a reason to ignore a ban on lighting fireworks during a drought—and lighting fireworks actually is a celebration of freedom.

Bill Moyers and Rebecca Gordon on the Meaning of the Fourth

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Sat, 04/07/2020 - 5:47am in

This week, I talked with Rebecca Gordon, a professor of ethics, about the 4th of July, the Movement for Black Lives and what she's hearing from her students who are ready for change. Continue reading

The post Bill Moyers and Rebecca Gordon on the Meaning of the Fourth appeared first on BillMoyers.com.

Visualizing the Connections among Philosophical Topics

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Fri, 03/07/2020 - 11:24pm in

Tags 

philosophy

Justin Reppert, a philosophy Ph.D. student at Fordham University, has created a fun tool that illustrates the connections between various philosophical topics, based on the “related links” sections of articles at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Philosophical Graphiti” charts the shortest paths of such links between two topics. Enter in two topics (as you begin to type suggestions to choose from show up in a window), and the result is a constellation of connections.

For example, here are the paths from “supererogation” to “neoplatonism”, each with 4 steps along the way:

Here’s “Quine” to “race”:

And here’s “Erotic Art” to “Lord Shaftesbury”:

I have to say I was not expecting that.

You can have some fun with Philosophical Graphiti yourself here.

Related: “New Map of SEP Based on Reciprocated Entries” and a variety of posts on philosophical visualizations.

The post Visualizing the Connections among Philosophical Topics appeared first on Daily Nous.

Should We Continue to Honor Hume With Buildings and Statues?

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Fri, 03/07/2020 - 10:14pm in

A campaign is underway to pressure the University of Edinburgh to rename Hume Tower.

The building, named for philosopher David Hume, was built in the early 1960s. Hume was born in Edinburgh, studied at the university, and worked there as a librarian.


[Hume Tower. Photograph by Simon Phipps.]

The call to remove Hume’s name from the building is part of a broader movement to reconsider the various public honors bestowed on those with racist views. A petition to rename the building currently has over 1,300 signatures.

Some have also urged the removal of the statue of David Hume from Edinburgh’s Royal Mile. The statue was erected in 1997 and is a popular attraction (and not just among traveling philosophers).

In his essay, “Of National Characters,” Hume says:

I am apt to suspect the negroes and in general all other species of men (for there are four or five different kinds) to be naturally inferior to the whites. There never was a civilized nation of any other complexion than white, nor even any individual eminent either in action or speculation; no ingenious manufactures amongst them, no arts, no sciences. On the other hand, the most rude and barbarous of the whites, such as the ancient GERMANS, the present TARTARS, have still something eminent about them in their valour, form of government, or some other particular. Such a uniform and constant difference could not happen in so many countries and ages, if nature had not made an original distinction betwixt these breeds of men. Not to mention our colonies, there are Negroe slaves dispersed all over Europe, of which none ever discovered any symptoms of ingenuity, tho’ low people, without education, will start up amongst us, and distinguish themselves in every profession. In JAMAICA indeed they talk of one negroe as a man of parts and learning; but ’tis likely he is admired for very slender accomplishments like a parrot, who speaks a few words plainly.

One might ask, as Aaron Garrett (Boston University) and Silvia Sebastiani (EHESS) do in their essay, “David Hume on Race” (ungated version here):

Should we care any more about what David Hume wrote and thought about race than about his views of on many other subjects that are not central to what we understand as his importance as a philosopher? And if we do indeed care about Hume’s thought about race should we care about what Hume thought on these issues any more than we do about other philosophers?

They answer “yes” to both of these questions.* Even if we agree with their answers, though, there is still the question of whether (and if so, how) we should continue to honor him with buildings and statues.

NOTE: As an experiment to improve the quality of discussion in the comments, those wishing to comment on this post must use their full names and submit working email addresses with their comments (email addresses are not published). No anonymous or pseudonymous handles may be used. Comments may take longer to appear than usual. If you haven’t done so in a while, please read the comments policy.

* See also these observations by Eric Schliesser (Amsterdam).

Related posts: “Statues, Monuments, & Philosophy“, “The Ethics of Honoring“.

The post Should We Continue to Honor Hume With Buildings and Statues? appeared first on Daily Nous.

“Hate Has No Home Here” and the Paradox of Tolerance 

Published by Anonymous (not verified) on Fri, 03/07/2020 - 12:39pm in

Tags 

philosophy

Is intolerance of intolerance, well, intolerant? Is hating hate hateful? 

Pages